To see accurate pricing, please choose your delivery country.
 
 
United States
£ GBP
All Shops

British Wildlife

8 issues per year 84 pages per issue Subscription only

British Wildlife is the leading natural history magazine in the UK, providing essential reading for both enthusiast and professional naturalists and wildlife conservationists. Published eight times a year, British Wildlife bridges the gap between popular writing and scientific literature through a combination of long-form articles, regular columns and reports, book reviews and letters.

Subscriptions from £33 per year

Conservation Land Management

4 issues per year 44 pages per issue Subscription only

Conservation Land Management (CLM) is a quarterly magazine that is widely regarded as essential reading for all who are involved in land management for nature conservation, across the British Isles. CLM includes long-form articles, events listings, publication reviews, new product information and updates, reports of conferences and letters.

Subscriptions from £26 per year
Academic & Professional Books  History & Other Humanities  Philosophy, Ethics & Religion

The Gaia Hypothesis Science on a Pagan Planet

By: Michael Ruse(Author)
251 pages, 16 b/w illustrations
NHBS
The Gaia Hypothesis is a rigorous analysis of its historical precursors and a piercing character study of Lovelock, explaining why Gaia was rejected by scientists but embraced by the public.
The Gaia Hypothesis
Click to have a closer look
Average customer review
  • The Gaia Hypothesis ISBN: 9780226731704 Hardback Oct 2013 Not in stock: Usually dispatched within 6 days
    £23.00
    #207738
Price: £23.00
About this book Contents Customer reviews Biography Related titles

About this book

In 1965 English scientist James Lovelock had a flash of insight: the Earth is not just teeming with life; the Earth, in some sense, is life. He mulled this revolutionary idea over for several years, first with his close friend the novelist William Golding, and then in an extensive collaboration with the American scientist Lynn Margulis. In the early 1970s, he finally went public with the Gaia hypothesis, the idea that everything happens for an end: the good of planet Earth.

Lovelock and Margulis were scorned by professional scientists, but the general public enthusiastically embraced Lovelock and his hypothesis. People joined Gaia groups; churches had Gaia services, sometimes with new music written especially for the occasion. There was a Gaia atlas, Gaia gardening, Gaia herbs, Gaia retreats, Gaia networking, and much more. And the range of enthusiasts was – and still is – broad.

In The Gaia Hypothesis: Science on a Pagan Planet, philosopher Michael Ruse, with his characteristic clarity and wit, uses Gaia and its history, its supporters and detractors, to illuminate the nature of science itself. Gaia emerged in the 1960s, a decade when authority was questioned and status and dignity stood for nothing, but its story is much older. Ruse traces Gaia's connection to Plato and a long history of goal-directed and holistic – or organicist – thinking and explains why Lovelock and Margulis' peers rejected it as pseudoscience.

But Ruse also shows why the project was a success. He argues that Lovelock and Margulis should be commended for giving philosophy firm scientific basis and for provoking important scientific discussion about the world as a whole, its homeostasis or – in this age of global environmental uncertainty – its lack thereof. Melding the world of science and technology with the world of feeling, mysticism, and religion, The Gaia Hypothesis: Science on a Pagan Planet will appeal to a broad range of readers, from students and scholars of the history and philosophy of science to anyone interested in New Age culture.

Contents

Preface
A Note on Interviews and Other Sources

INTRODUCTION
1 THE GAIA HYPOTHESIS
2 THE PARADOX
3 THE PAGAN PLANET
4 MECHANISM
5 ORGANICISM
6 HYLOZOISM
7 GAIA REVISITED
8 UNDERSTANDING
ENVOI

References
Index

Customer Reviews (1)

  • Challenging but satisfying
    By Leon (NHBS Catalogue Editor) 29 Jul 2023 Written for Hardback


    In The Gaia Hypothesis, professor of philosophy Michael Ruse analyses the reception of Lovelock's ideas and delves into the historical and philosophical precursors to the notion of Earth as a living planet. An intellectually rigorous if sometimes challenging book, it gives a very satisfying overview of why Lovelock got the reception he did and, for me, as the first book by Ruse I read, marks him as a notable writer to keep an eye on.

    Ruse opens with an introduction to the conception and basic premise of the Gaia hypothesis and the cast of characters. Scientists initially did not take it seriously. When it became clear that Gaia was not going away, they rained down both scorn and well-deserved critique on it. The general public, on the other hand, lapped it up. People were losing their religion while a countercultural revolution was in full swing. "Earth as an organism was just the vision, just the metaphor, for which many individuals and groups were searching" (p. 37). Ruse sees a paradox here. How is it that scientists rejected a fellow scientist-inventor, while a progressive counterculture embraced the ideas of a man funded by the military and the industry?

    To resolve this paradox, Ruse provides a historical analysis in chapters 3 to 6 that form the core of this book. It was also the section that I found challenging in places, but that will be because I have no background in classical philosophy and metaphysics. Given this, I am stepping onto some very thin ice here, and I apologise in advance to all philosophers reading this if I am about to butcher some of your favourite concepts. That said, here is my understanding of the relevant points being made.

    Ruse starts with Plato and Aristotle and their ideas on the nature of reality. They introduced different forms of teleology, which is the explanation of phenomena by arguing why—for what purpose or to what end—things happen in the world, rather than explaining what is causing them. Furthermore, no distinction was made between body and soul. Next to the soul animating the body (hylomorphism), of relevance to the Gaia hypothesis is that this animatedness extended to all matter, something Ruse refers to as "world soul thinking" or hylozoism. This notion waxed and waned over the centuries and an important hallmark of the Scientific Revolution was a gradual banishing of final causes. We moved towards an understanding in terms of mechanical metaphors, reductionism, and of matter as inert and without purpose. In particular, Ruse details the rise of mechanistic thinking and the expulsion of final causes in the two disciplines relevant to Gaia: geology and evolutionary biology.

    Nevertheless, Plato's philosophy and the notion of a world soul persisted. Ruse traces a line through the German Romantic movement and American transcendentalism to the 19th-century rise of organicism, a school of thought in biology that erupted from intellectual hotbeds such as the universities of Harvard and Chicago. As defined here by Ruse, it stands in contrast to mechanism and argues that whole entities such as organisms are emergent properties. In the wider world, meanwhile, hylozoism lived on in e.g. deep ecology, ecofeminism, anthroposophy, and New Age paganism.

    An important piece in the puzzle is Lovelock himself. Ruse provides a piercing if fair character study in the last two chapters. He is fair by pointing out that Lovelock demonstrated "outstanding talents" (p. 179) and his work with NASA showed "he did not break with traditional science; he simply did it better than anyone else" (p. 180). Ruse judges him to be "basically a very conventional scientist [who] was rightly elected to the Royal Society" (p. 181). However, this is no hagiography. His points confirm my suspicions that, frankly, Lovelock increasingly became a crank later in life. His response to criticism was "partly petulant" (p. 147), his attitude one of "cocky self-assurance [and] hubris" (p. 187). He was proud to be an independent scientist who dared to think outside the box and he felt disdain for academic institutes and peer review. The bigger problem Ruse highlights is that "Lovelock was not a biologist, didn't think like one, and wasn't about to start now" (p. 155). Lacking knowledge of classic philosophy, he was ignorant of the history of banishing teleology from evolutionary biology. He was "not a deep thinker [but] a tinkerer, an inventor, an instrument maker—and such people do think teleologically" (p. 187). Straying far outside his area of expertise and possessed of both ignorance and innocence, he "clearly had no idea of what he was embarking upon" (p. 186).

    And then there was the company that Lovelock kept, with Ruse focusing on two people. First, there was the Nobel Prize–winning author William Golding who suggested the term Gaia. He used to be deeply involved with anthroposophy and was thus receptive to Lovelock's idea of Earth as a living being. Ruse beautifully summarizes his contribution thus: "The idea was Lovelock's, but the facilitator was Golding" (p. 183). Second, there was Lynn Margulis, the headstrong scientist who finally had won acclaim with her hypothesis of endosymbiosis but then went off the rails by seeing symbiosis everywhere. Though she continued to support Lovelock's cause throughout her life, they only co-published an initial batch of papers after which they gradually drifted apart.

    How does all of the above help resolve the paradox of how Gaia was received? In a nutshell, public reception was positive because Gaia resonated with the spirit of the times and Lovelock was affable in his interactions, resulting in little scrutiny of either him or his ideas. The scientific reception was more hostile for several reasons. Lovelock neither could nor wanted to rid his idea of its implicit teleology. Having given it a fair hearing, Gaia was found wanting as a useful hypothesis. Gaia also entered the room when science was beleaguered by forces within and without. Finally, the enthusiastic and uncritical public reception made scientists wary. To put it mildly, Gaia "obviously did and still does on balance appeal more to those challenging conventional norms" (p. 200). Ruse concludes that "despite general agreement that Gaia had pushed thinking in some important directions, by around 2000 the Gaia hypothesis [....] had lost momentum" (p. 220).

    Ruse tries to put a brave face on it when finishing the book: "no more talk of failure. Lovelock and Margulis were big people with a big vision. Whether science likes it or not, the vision lives on" (p. 224). To me, that belies the critical and piercing analysis in this book. The Gaia Hypothesis provides tremendous context, and will primarly appeal to a more intellectual audience, given Ruse's interest in history and philosophy.
    Was this helpful to you? Yes No

Biography

Michael Ruse is the Lucyle T. Werkmeister Professor of Philosophy and director of the Program in the History and Philosophy of Science at Florida State University. He is the author or editor of nearly thirty books, including Science and Spirituality and The Darwinian Revolution, the latter published by the University of Chicago Press.

By: Michael Ruse(Author)
251 pages, 16 b/w illustrations
NHBS
The Gaia Hypothesis is a rigorous analysis of its historical precursors and a piercing character study of Lovelock, explaining why Gaia was rejected by scientists but embraced by the public.
Media reviews

"[Ruse's] treatment is thought-provoking and original, as you would expect from this perceptive, irrepressible philosopher of biology."
– New Scientist

"Fascinating [...] The book is full of empathetic, insightful, and often very funny portraits of Margulis, Lovelock, and a community of other figures associated with Gaia and its histories. It is also a wonderfully lively and readable narrative."
– Carla Nappi, New Books in Science, Technology, and Society

"Few philosophers have blended the history and philosophy of science more successfully than Michael Ruse. And no contemporary scholar has played a more active role in establishing and maintaining the boundaries of science. In this riveting examination of the Gaia hypothesis – that is, the claim that Earth is a living planet – Ruse even-handedly applies his expertise to dissecting a controversial case where science, pseudoscience, and religion all came into play."
– Ronald L. Numbers, University of Wisconsin–Madison

"Written with Michael Ruse's trademark combination of storytelling verve and philosophical insight, this book offers a fascinating history of the appealing but scientifically heretical idea that the earth is in some sense alive. Ruse not only recounts the successes and failures of this intriguing notion, but along the way poses searching questions about the nature of science and its popular reception."
– Peter Harrison, author of The Fall of Man and the Foundations of Science

"Michael Ruse has a habit of tackling big ideas in the history and philosophy of science, and there is hardly any idea bigger than the Gaia hypothesis. Ruse situates James Lovelock and Lynn Margulis's theory of Earth as a living, self-regulating organism within several contexts, ranging from their personal biographies to the long history of mechanism and organicism in the life sciences. The trek through the past helps make sense of both the immense popularity of Gaia among the lay public and the hostility it faced from professional scientists, as Ruse contends that they are both part of the same process."
– Michael D. Gordin, author of The Pseudoscience Wars

Current promotions
New and Forthcoming BooksNHBS Moth TrapBritish Wildlife MagazineBuyers Guides